Vis enkel innførsel

dc.contributor.authorSolberg, Carl Ten_US
dc.contributor.authorGamlund, Espenen_US
dc.date.accessioned2016-06-24T11:45:15Z
dc.date.available2016-06-24T11:45:15Z
dc.date.issued2016-04-14
dc.PublishedBMC Medical Ethics. 2016 Apr 14;17(1):21eng
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/1956/12186
dc.description.abstractBackground The state of the world is one with scarce medical resources where longevity is not equally distributed. Given such facts, setting priorities in health entails making difficult yet unavoidable decisions about which lives to save. The business of saving lives works on the assumption that longevity is valuable and that an early death is worse than a late death. There is a vast literature on health priorities and badness of death, separately. Surprisingly, there has been little cross-fertilisation between the academic fields of priority setting and badness of death. Our aim is to connect philosophical discussions on the badness of death to contemporary debates in health priorities. Discussion Two questions regarding death are especially relevant to health priorities. The first question is why death is bad. Death is clearly bad for others, such as family, friends and society. Many philosophers also argue that death can be bad for those who die. This distinction is important for health priorities, because it concerns our fundamental reasons for saving lives. The second question is, ‘When is the worst time to die?’ A premature death is commonly considered worse than a late death. Thus, the number of good life years lost seems to matter to the badness of death. Concerning young individuals, some think the death of infants is worse than the death of adolescents, while others have contrary intuitions. Our claim is that to prioritise between age groups, we must consider the question of when it is worst to die. Conclusions Deprivationism provides a more plausible approach to health priorities than Epicureanism. If Deprivationism is accepted, we will have a firmer basis for claiming that individuals, in addition to having a health loss caused by morbidity, will have a loss of good life years due to mortality. Additionally, Deprivationism highlights the importance of age and values for health priorities. Regarding age, both variants of Deprivationism imply that stillbirths are included in the Global Burden of Disease. Finally, we suggest that the Time-Relative Interest Account may serve as an alternative to the discounting and age weighting previously applied in the Global Burden of Disease.en_US
dc.language.isoengeng
dc.publisherBioMed Centraleng
dc.rightsAttribution CC BY 4.0eng
dc.rights.urihttp://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0eng
dc.subjectAge weightingeng
dc.subjectBadness of deatheng
dc.subjectWelfare losseng
dc.subjectDiscountingeng
dc.subjectDeprivation accounteng
dc.subjectEpicureanismeng
dc.subjectGlobal burden of diseaseeng
dc.subjectHealth prioritieseng
dc.subjectMorbidityeng
dc.subjectTime-relative interest accounteng
dc.titleThe badness of death and priorities in healthen_US
dc.typePeer reviewed
dc.typeJournal article
dc.date.updated2016-04-14T06:02:16Z
dc.description.versionpublishedVersionen_US
dc.rights.holderCopyright Solberg and Gamlund 2016
dc.identifier.doihttps://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-016-0104-6
dc.subject.nsiVDP::Medisinske Fag: 700en_US


Tilhørende fil(er)

Thumbnail

Denne innførselen finnes i følgende samling(er)

Vis enkel innførsel

Attribution CC BY 4.0
Med mindre annet er angitt, så er denne innførselen lisensiert som Attribution CC BY 4.0